Abstract
Models, theories, and laws are important in both philosophy of science and science education. However, there is a continuous discussion among philosophers of science about these concepts, and it is difficult to achieve consensus. Similarly, in science education there is a continuous debate that leads to controversies. In the face of these difficulties, some scholars have suggested that we follow “science as practiced by scientists” (Levere, Interchange, 37, 115–128; 2006). History of science, however, shows that on many occasions what the scientists publish in their original papers is quite different from what they actually did. Given the complexity of the issues involved, some science educators have suggested that after having adopted empiricism and historicism in the past, science educators now need to adopt the model-based view based on naturalized philosophy of science (Duschl and Grandy, Science & Education, 22(9), 2109–2139; 2013). The model-based view seems to emphasize cognitive psychology and ignore the historical reconstructions. Ronald Giere’s naturalism provided one possible alternative by placing the philosophy of science at the same level as history of science, referred to as perspectivism (Giere 2006a, b). Other philosophers (Denis Phillips and Harvey Siegel) consider that the historical reconstructions can even extend the naturalistic philosophy of science. One way to retain the history of science in the curriculum is to follow the tactics and strategies of eighteenth and nineteenth century scientists as suggested by James Conant. In this context, I have presented evidence of various episodes from twentieth century science that can also qualify for inclusion in the science curriculum, such as: the oil drop experiment, the alpha particle experiments, the atomic models and the ensuing controversies, Millikan’s determination of Planck’s constant and rejection of Einstein’s quantum hypothesis, the wave-particle duality, and Martin Perl’s discovery of the Tau Lepton. An important underlying aspect of these historical episodes is that scientific knowledge is perspectival rather than absolutely objective, leading to the tentative nature of scientific theories. Furthermore, besides underdetermination some contingency is always present in any science, that is, the same experimental observations can be explained by rival theories and their acceptance may depend on the order in which these are presented to the scientific community (e.g., quantum mechanics and bond formation).
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
References
Adey, P., Shayer, M., & Yates, C. (2001). Thinking science: The curriculum materials of the CASE project (3rd ed.). London: Routledge.
Bohr, N. (1913). On the constitution of atoms and molecules. Part 1. Philosophical Magazine, 26(Series 6), 1–25.
BouJaoude, S., Salloum, S., & Abd-El-Khalick, F. (2004). Relationships between selective cognitive variables and students’ ability to solve chemistry problems. International Journal of Science Education, 26(1), 63–84.
Bruner, J. (1977). The process of education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Calver, N. (2013). Sir Peter Medawar: Science, creativity and the popularization of Karl Popper. Notes and Records of the Royal Society, 67, 301–314.
Campbell, D. T. (1988). Can we be scientific in applied social science? In E. S. Overman (Ed.), Methodology and epistemology for social science (pp. 315–333). Chicago: University of Chicago Press (first published 1984 in Evaluation Studies Review Annual), (pp. 315–333).
Carruthers, P., Stich, S., & Siegal, M. (Eds.). (2002). The cognitive basis of science. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Chi, M. T. H. (2005). Commonsense conceptions of emergent processes. Why some misconceptions are robust. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 14, 161–199.
Clement, J. (1998). Expert novice similarities and instruction using analogies. International Journal of Science Education, 20(10), 1271–1286.
Conant, J. B. (1947). On understanding science: A historical approach. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Cooper, L. N. (1992). Physics: Structure and meaning. Hanover: University Press of New England.
Darrigol, O. (2009). A simplified genesis of quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 40, 151–166.
Duschl, R. A., & Duncan, R. G. (2009). Reply to both questions. In S. Tobias & T. M. Duffy (Eds.), Constructivist instruction: Success or failure? (p. 324). New York: Routledge.
Duschl, R. A., & Grandy, R. (2013). Two views about explicitly teaching nature of science. Science & Education, 22(9), 2109–2139.
Earman, J. (2004). Laws, symmetry and symmetry breaking: Invariance, conservation principles and objectivity. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 1227–1241.
Ehenhaft, F. (1941). The microcoulomb experiment. Philosophy of Science, 8, 403–457.
Einstein, A. (1905). Über einen Erzeugung und Verwandlung des Lichtes betreffenden heuristischen Gesichtspunkt. Annalen der Physik, 17, 132–148.
Galison, P. (2008). Ten problems in history and philosophy of science. Isis, 99, 111–124.
Gieger, H., & Marsden, E. (1909). On a diffuse reflection of the alpha particles. Proceedings of the Royal Society (Vol. lxxxii). London: Royal Society.
Giere, R. N. (1999). Science without laws. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Giere, R. N. (2006a). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Giere, R. N. (2010). Naturalism. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 213–223). London: Routledge.
Giere, R. N. (2014). Email to author dated March 19, 2014 after reading a preliminary version of Chapter 2, reproduced with permission.
Gooday, G., Lynch, J. M., Wilson, K. G., & Barsky, C. K. (2008). Does science education need the history of science? Isis, 99, 322–330.
Heilbron, J. L., & Kuhn, T. (1969). The genesis of the Bohr atom. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 1, 211–290.
Hodson, D. (2009). Teaching and learning about science: Language, theories, methods, history, traditions and values. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.
Hodson, D., & Wong, S. L. (2014). From the horse’s mouth: Why scientists’ views are crucial to nature of science understanding. International Journal of Science Education, 36(16), 2639–2665.
Holton, G. (1978a). Subelectrons, presuppositions, and the Millikan-Ehrenhaft dispute. Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, 9, 161–224.
Holton, G. (1978b). The scientific imagination: Case studies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holton, G. (1999). R.A. Millikan’s struggle with the meaning of Planck’s constant. Physics in Perspective, 1, 231–237.
Kitchener, R. F. (1986). Piaget’s theory of knowledge: Genetic epistemology and scientific reason. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Kitcher, P. (2007). Living with Darwin: Evolution, design, and the future of faith. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kitcher, P. (2011). Epistemology without history is blind. Erkenntnis, 75, 505–524.
Klahr, D. (2009). Question: Klahr. In S. Tobias & T. M. Duffy (Eds.), Constructivist instruction: Success or failure? (p. 323). New York: Routledge.
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–195). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 33–49.
Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond positivism and relativism: Theory, method and evidence. Boulder: Westview Press (Division of HarperCollins).
Lawson, A. E. (1983). Predicting science achievement: The role of developmental level, disembedding level, mental capacity, prior knowledge, and beliefs. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 20, 117–129.
Lawson, A. E. (1985). A review of research on formal reasoning and science instruction. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 22, 569–617.
Lehrer, R., & Schauble, L. (2012). Seeding evolutionary by engaging children in modeling its foundations. Science Education, 96(4), 701–724.
Margenau, H. (1950). The nature of physical reality. New York: McGraw-Hill.
Medawar, P. B. (1967). The art of the soluble. London: Methuen.
Millikan, R. A. (1913). On the elementary electrical charge and the Avogadro constant. Physical Review, 2, 109–143.
Millikan, R. A. (1916). A direct photoelectric determination of Planck’s ‘h’. Physical Review, 7, 355–388.
Millikan, R. A. (1950). The autobiography of Robert A. Millikan. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc.
National Research Council, NRC. (2007). Taking science to school: Learning and teaching science kindergarten to eighth grade. In R. A. Duschl, H. A. Schweingruber, & A. W. Shouse (Eds.), Center for education, division of behavioral and social sciences. Washington, DC: The National Academy Press.
Newton-Smith, W. H. (1981). The rationality of science. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Niaz, M. (1988). Manipulation of M-demand of chemistry problems and its effect on student performance: A neo-Piagetian study. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 25, 643–657.
Niaz, M. (1989). The relationship between M-demand, algorithms, and problem solving: A neo-Piagetian analysis. Journal of Chemical Education, 66, 422–424.
Niaz, M. (1991). Role of the epistemic subject in Piaget’s genetic epistemology and its importance for science education. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 28, 569–580.
Niaz, M. (1992). From Piaget’s epistemic subject to Pascual-Leone’s metasubject: Epistemic transition in the constructivist-rationalist theory of cognitive development. International Journal of Psychology, 27(6), 443–457.
Niaz, M. (1995c). Piaget’s epistemic subject: A reply to Shayer. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 32, 1003–1005.
Niaz, M. (1993). If Piaget’s epistemic subject is dead, shall we bury the scientific research methodology of idealization. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 30(7), 809–812.
Niaz, M. (1997). How early can children understand some form of scientific reasoning? Perceptual and Motor Skills, 85, 1272–1274.
Niaz, M. (1998b). From cathode rays to alpha particles to quantum of action: A rational reconstruction of structure of the atom and its implications for chemistry textbooks. Science Education, 82, 527–552.
Niaz, M. (2005). An appraisal of the controversial nature of the oil drop experiment: Is closure possible? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56(4), 681–702.
Niaz, M. (2009). Critical appraisal of physical science as a human enterprise: Dynamics of scientific progress. Dordrecht: Springer.
Niaz, M. (2010). Are we teaching science as practiced by scientists? American Journal of Physics, 78, 5–6.
Niaz, M. (2012a). From ‘science in the making’ to understanding the nature of science: An overview for science educators. New York: Routledge.
Niaz, M., & Lawson, A. E. (1985). Balancing chemical equations: The role of developmental level and mental capacity. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 22, 41–51.
Niaz, M., & Marcano, C. (2012). Reconstruction of wave-particle duality and its implications for general chemistry textbooks. Dordrecht: Springer.
Niaz, M., & Robinson, W. R. (1992). Manipulation of logical structure of chemistry problems and its effects on student performance. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 29, 211–226.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1970). A mathematical model for the transition rule in Piaget’s developmental stages. Acta Psychologica, 32, 301–345.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1978). Compounds, confounds, and models in developmental information processing: A reply to Trabasso and Foellinger. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 26, 18–40.
Pascual-Leone, J. (1987). Organismic processes for neo-Piagetian theories: A dialectical causal account of cognitive development. International Journal of Psychology, 22, 531–570.
Perl, M. L. (2004). The discovery of the Tau Lepton and the changes in elementary-particle physics in forty years. Physics in Perspective, 6, 401–427.
Phillips, D. C. (2005). The contested nature of empirical educational research (and why philosophy of education offers little help). Journal of Philosophy of Education, 39, 577–597.
Phillips, D. C. (2014). Email to author, dated Feb. 6, 2014, reproduced with permission.
Piaget, J., & Garcia, R. (1989). Psychogenesis and the history of science. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rutherford, E. (1911). The scattering of alpha and beta particles by matter and the structure of the atom. Philosophical Magazine, 21, 669–688.
Sawyer, R. K. (Ed.). (2006). The Cambridge handbook of the learning sciences. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Schwab, J. J. (1974). The concept of the structure of a discipline. In E. W. Eisner & E. Vallance (Eds.), Conflicting conceptions of curriculum (pp. 162–175). Berkeley: McCutchan Publishing Corp.
Siegel, H. (2013). Review of Stathis Psillos and Martin Curd (eds): The Routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 729–731), 2008. New York: Routledge. Science & Education, 22(3), 729–731
Siegel, H. (2014). Email to author, dated Feb. 5, 2014, reproduced with permission.
Stamovlasis, D., & Tsaparlis, G. (2012). Applying catastrophe theory to an information processing model of problem solving in science education. Science Education, 96, 392–410.
St Clair-Thompson, H. L., Overton, T., & Bugler, M. (2012). Mental capacity and working memory in chemistry: Algorithmic versus open-ended problem solving. Chemistry Education Research and Practice, 13, 484–489.
Stuewer, R. H. (1975). The Compton effect: Turning point in physics. New York: Science History Publications.
Tsaparlis, G. (2014b). Cognitive demand. In R. Gunstone (Ed.), Encyclopedia of science education (pp. 1–4). Dordrecht: Springer.
Tsaparlis, G., Kousathana, M., & Niaz, M. (1998). Molecular-equilibrium problems: Manipulation of logical structure and of M-demand, and their effect on student performance. Science Education, 82, 437–454.
Weinberg, S. (1980). Conceptual foundations of the unified theory of weak and electromagnetic interactions. Reviews of Modern Physics, 52, 515–523.
Weinberg, S. (2001). Physics and history. In J. A. Labinger & H. M. Collins (Eds.), The one culture: A conversation about science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Wilson, D. (1983). Rutherford: Simple genius. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Worrall, J. (2010). Theory-change in science. In S. Psillos & M. Curd (Eds.), The routledge companion to philosophy of science (pp. 281–291). New York: Routledge.
Wu, H.-K., & Shah, P. (2004). Exploring visuospatial thinking in chemistry learning. Science Education, 88, 465–492.
Yuan, K., Steedle, J., Shavelson, R., Alonzo, A., & Oppezzo, M. (2006). Working memory, fluid intelligence and science learning. Educational Research Review, 1, 83–98.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland
About this chapter
Cite this chapter
Niaz, M. (2016). Models, Theories, and Laws in Philosophy of Science and Science Education. In: Chemistry Education and Contributions from History and Philosophy of Science. Science: Philosophy, History and Education. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26248-2_2
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26248-2_2
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-319-26246-8
Online ISBN: 978-3-319-26248-2
eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)